[SOLVED] 代写 R algorithm Scheme math graph statistic Bayesian theory The Fallacy of Placing Confidence in Confidence Intervals

30 $

File Name: 代写_R_algorithm_Scheme_math_graph_statistic_Bayesian_theory_The_Fallacy_of_Placing_Confidence_in_Confidence_Intervals.zip
File Size: 1130.4 KB

SKU: 1882324948 Category: Tags: , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , ,

Or Upload Your Assignment Here:


The Fallacy of Placing Confidence in Confidence Intervals
Richard D. Morey and Rink Hoekstra University of Groningen
Michael D. Lee University of CaliforniaIrvine
Jeffrey N. Rouder University of Missouri
EricJan Wagenmakers University of Amsterdam
Interval estimatesestimates of parameters that include an allowance for sampling uncertaintyhave long been touted as a key component of statistical analyses. There are several kinds of interval estimates, but the most popular are confidence intervals CIs: intervals that contain the true parameter value in some known proportion of repeated samples, on average. The width of confidence intervals is thought to index the precision of an estimate; the parameter values contained within a CI are thought to be more plausible than those outside the interval; and the confidence coefficient of the interval typically 95 is thought to index the plausibility that the true parameter is included in the interval. We show in a number of examples that CIs do not necessarily have any of these properties, and generally lead to incoherent inferences. For this reason, we recommend against the use of the method of CIs for inference.
You keep using that word. I do not think it means what you think it means.
Inigo Montoya, The Princess Bride 1987
The development of statistics over the past century has seen the proliferation of methods designed to make infer ences from data. Methods vary widely in their philosophical foundations, the questions they are supposed to address, and their frequency of use in practice. One popular and widely promoted class of methods are interval estimates, which in clude frequentist confidence intervals, Bayesian credible in tervals and highest posterior density HPD intervals, fiducial intervals, and likelihood intervals. These procedures differ in their philosophical foundation and computation, but infor mally are all designed to be estimates of a parameter that ac count for measurement or sampling uncertainty by yielding a range of values for the parameter instead of a single value.
Of the many kinds of interval estimates, the most popular is the confidence interval CI. Confidence intervals are intro duced in almost all introductory statistics texts; they are rec ommended or required by the methodological guidelines of many prominent journals e.g., Psychonomics Society, 2012; Wilkinsonthe Task Force on Statistical Inference, 1999; and they form the foundation of proposed methodological reformers programs Cumming, 2014; Loftus, 1996. How ever, there is a tremendous amount of confusion in among re searchers, methodologists, and textbook authors about what
7698 words. Address correspondence to Richard D. Morey richarddmoreygmail.com. We thank Mijke Rhemtulla for help ful discussion during the drafting of the manuscript.
exactly a confidence interval is and how it may be inter preted. We believe that the confusion about what CIs are drives their promotion; if researchers understood what CIs actually are, and what inferences that can or cannot support, they would not be promoted as commonly as they are. Our goal is to alleviate confusion about CIs and to call into ques tion whether they can be used for sound inference.
We begin by precisely defining confidence intervals. We then outline three common myths about confidence interval that have been perpetuated by proponents of confidence in tervals. Using several examples, we show how it is not nec essary that confidence intervals have any of the properties commonly ascribed to them; that is, confidence intervals, as general inference tools, have been misrepresented. Finally, we discuss methods thatunder certain assumptionsdo have the properties that researchers desire.
Confidence Intervals
In a classic paper, Neyman 1937 laid the formal founda tion for confidence intervals. Before defining confidence in tervals, we describe the practical problem that Neyman saw confidence intervals as solving. Suppose a researcher is in terested in estimating a parameter, which we may call . This parameter could be a population mean, an effect size, a vari ance, or any other quantity of interest. Neyman suggests that researchers perform the following three steps:
a. Perform an experiment, collecting the relevant data.
b. Compute two numbersthe smaller of which we can call
L, the greater of which Uforming an interval L,U according to an algorithm.
DRAFT

2 MOREY ET AL.
c. StatethatLUthatis,thatisintheinterval.
This recommendation is justified by choosing an algorithm for step b such that in the long run, the researchers claim in step c will be correct, on average, X of the time. A confidence interval is any interval computed using such a procedure.
Definition 1 Confidence interval A X confidence inter val for a parameteris an interval L,U generated by an algorithm that in repeated sampling has an X probability of containing the true value ofNeyman, 1937.
Although skepticism about the usefulness of confidence intervals began as soon as Neyman laid out the theory e.g., the discussion of Neyman, 19341, confidence intervals have grown in popularity to be the most widely used interval es timators. Perhaps the most commonly used CI is the CI for the mean of the normal distribution with unknown variance.
1
60 80
107 CIs contain the true value 53.5
100 120 140

x t
N
s
Figure 1. 200 random 50 CIs for a normal mean with un known variance, based on 2 draws from a Normal100, 152distribution. Dark blue lines denote CIs that contain the true mean; light red lines denote those that do not. CIs are sorted by length.
Myths of Confidence
Confidence intervals are described broadly as tools for ex tracting the necessary information about the parameter from the data. However, the relationship between the definition of the confidence interval and anything a researcher would want to know is unclear: we might know the average properties of the procedure, but what implications does this have for infer ence from a specific interval? Various heuristic explanations are used by textbook authors and proponents of confidence intervals in the literature to help bridge the gap between the theoretical definition of the confidence interval and proper ties that are important to analysts, such as the plausibility of specific parameter values or the precision of an estimate. In this section, we explain how the various heuristic expla nations of confidence intervals are actually myths: they are not true of confidence intervals in general. We present two examples that show how the logic of inference by CI fails.
Example 1: The lost submarine
1For instance, in this discussion Bowley states Does the con fidence interval really lead us towards what we needthe chance that in the universe which we are sampling the proportion is within these certain limits? I think it does not. I think we are in the posi tion of knowing that either an improbable event has occurred or the proportion in the population is within the limits. To balance these things we must make an estimate and form a judgment as to the like lihood of the proportion in the universe that is, a prior probabilitythe very thing that is supposed to be eliminated.
2The more typical choice of 95 confidence is, of course, arbi trary. All of the points we make in this paper extend to 95 CIs and N2, with the drawback that the arguments would be more mathematically involved and less transparent. Because our goal is to demonstrate that the logic of using confidence intervals for infer ence is flawed, we opt to use the simplest case.
where xand s are the sample mean and standard deviation, N is the sample size, and t the quantile from Students tN1 distribution chosen such that
PrtN1tX
for an X CI. This confidence interval is taught to first year statistics students all over the world and used in papers throughout the scientific literature.
Figure 1 shows 200 random 50 confidence intervals, all
constructed from draws of sample size N2 from the same
Normal100,152 population. Some of the confidence inter
vals, denoted by dark lines, include the true mean 100;
others do not and are denoted with light lines. Of this sam
ple of 200 confidence intervals, 107 53.5 contain the true
value; if we were to continue sampling more CIs, this pro
portion would approach the confidence coefficient X50.
Note that with two observations t1 and sx1x2
2, meaning that the 50 Students t CI is simply the interval between the two observations. We make use of the simplicity
of the 50 CI with two observations throughout.2
The definition of a confidence interval seems, on its face, straightforward: a CI is an interval generated by some pro cedure that creates intervals containing the true value of a parameter in some fixed proportion of repeated samples, on average. Put another way, if one were to always make the dichotomous claim that the true value is in a specific interval computed from the procedure, one would be correct in that same proportion of repeated samples. Confidence is thus an average property of a procedure. It is conceptually help ful, therefore, to distinguish between a confidence procedure CP and a confidence interval CI. For the purposes of this paper we will use the term confidence procedure to denote the algorithm, and confidence interval to denote specific re
alizations from the algorithm.

FUNDAMENTAL CONFIDENCE FALLACY 3
Posterior
Cred. Int.
Conf. Int. 2
Conf. Int. 1
Bubbles
AB
10 55 10 10 55 10 Location Location
The statisticians opinion has been guided by the claims made by the advocates of CIs. The relationship between CIs and precision, or power, is often cited as one of the primary reasons they should be used over null hypothesis significance tests e.g., CummingFinch, 2005; Cumming, 2014; FidlerLoftus, 2009; Loftus, 1993, 1996. For instance, Cum ming 2014 writes that long confidence intervals CIs will soon let us know if our experiment is weak and can give only imprecise estimates, and Young and Lewis 1997 state that the width of the CI gives us information on the preci sion of the point estimate.
One of the rescue workers, however, is skeptical. She notes that there are a wide range of locations that are possi ble for the location of the hatch. Because the craft is 10 me ters long, no bubble can originate more than 5 meters from hatch. Given two bubbles, the only possible locations for the hatch are within 5 meters of both bubbles. These values are shown as the shaded region in Figure 2A labeled poste rior. The bubbles themselves give no reason to prefer any of these locations over another. The skeptical rescue worker says that because the second bubble was so close to the first, collectively the bubbles have actually provided very impre cise information. She suggests waiting for more bubbles be fore dropping the line.
The statistician, on the authority of the many advocates of confidence intervals, convinces the rescuers to drop the line inside the 50 CI. The rescue line misses the hatch by 3.75 meters. By the time the rescue workers realize they have missed the hatch, there is no more time for another attempt. All crew on board the submersible are lost.
The statistician has fallen victim to a myth about confi dence intervals that we dub the precision error:
Myth 1 The Precision Error The width of a confidence interval indicates the precision of our knowledge about the parameter. Narrow confidence intervals show precise knowl edge, while wide confidence errors show imprecise knowl edge.
There is no necessary connection between the precision of an estimate and the size of a confidence interval. In the case of the submarine, the narrow confidence interval yielded im precise imprecise information about the location of the sub marine hatch. In fact, as we shall see, the narrowness of an interval from CP1 and the precision are actually inversely related, as the next situation will make clear.
Oddly enough, a second boat is in a similar situation to the first half a world away. The researchers on the boat have contact with their submersible, and like the first boat are planning to mount a rescue using the distinctive bubbles. They consult their statistician, who advises them to wait for
3This example was adapted from Welch 1939 and Berger and Wolpert 1988.
Figure 2. Submersible rescue attempts. See text.
A 10meterlong research submersible with several peo ple on board has lost contact with its surface support vessel. The submersible has a rescue hatch exactly halfway along its length, to which the support vessel will drop a rescue line. Because the rescuers only get one rescue attempt, it is cru cial that when the line is dropped to the craft in the deep water that the line be as close as possible to this hatch. The researchers on the support vessel do not know where the sub mersible is, but they do know that it forms distinctive bub bles. These bubbles could form anywhere along the crafts length, independently, with equal probability, and float to the surface where they can be seen by the support vessel.3
The situation is shown in Figure 2A. The rescue hatch is the unknown location , and the bubbles can rise anywhere from 5 meters the bow of the submersible to 5 meters the stern of the submersible. The rescuers want to use these bubbles to learn where the hatch is located, so they consult the frequentist statistician on board. The statistician, being an advocate of the use of confidence intervals, tells the res cuers how confidence intervals can be used to estimate the location of the hatch. He notes that the location of these first two bubbles form a 50 confidence interval for the , because there is a 50 probability that two bubbles will be on opposite sides of the hatch. In more familiar terms, the statistician has chosen the 50 confidence procedure
xx 1x 2, 2
where x1 and x2 are the locations of the first and second bub bles, respectively, and xis the mean location. The statistician justifies this confidence procedure on the grounds that it is the same as the 50 Students t procedure with N2. We denote this procedure Confidence Procedure 1 CP1.
The rescuers see the first two bubbles, shown as circles in Figure 2A. The two bubbles are very close together, yielding the narrow 50 confidence interval shown above the bub bles. The statistician excitedly reports to the rescue workers that this narrow CI indicates that the knowledge of the hatch location is quite precise, and that he is 50 certain that the hatch is in the confidence interval. He advises them to drop the rescue line.

4 MOREY ET AL.
the first two bubbles and use a 50 CI from Confidence Procedure 1. While the rescue team waits for the bubbles to appear, the statistician notes that CP1 does not directly make use of the known variance of the bubble locations. She quickly computes an alternative 50 confidence procedure, which we denote Confidence Procedure 2 CP2:
5
x 5 2
The second statistician notes that the interval from CP2 is 2.93 meters wide. Thinking that all values within this interval are likely, she advises risking waiting for a few more bub bles to narrow the confidence interval. However, a perceptive rescue worker challenges the statistician. He notes that they know very precisely where the hatch must be: halfway be tween the two bubbles! The bubbles were almost as far apart as they could be, which means they must have come from opposite ends of the craft. If they came from opposite ends of the craft, then the hatch must be almost exactly in the mid dle. The only possible locations for the hatch are shown in the top line of Figure 2B, labeled posterior. In fact, nearly all of the values contained in the 50 CIs computed from CP1 and CP2 are impossible; the hatch could not possibly be located there.
The rescue worker advises to ignore the statistician and to drop the rescue line halfway between the bubbles. The argu ment of the rescue worker convinces the other rescue work ers. The rescue line meets the hatch, and all crew members aboard the submersible are saved.
In the rescue attempts of both submarines, the statisticians used the same logic recommended by the advocates of con fidence intervals in an effort to determine the location of the submarine hatch. In both cases, the judgment of the statis tician was flawed. We now consider how the confidence in terval could be so misleading. In the example, the likelihood and precision errors are easily seen; CIs can contain mostly impossible values, and the precision of an estimate available in the data can be inversely related to the narrowness of the CI, or not related at all. The logic of the likelihood and pre cision interpretations of CIs simply do not follow from the definition of a confidence procedure; some confidence inter vals may have these properties, others may not.
If the precision and likelihood interpretations of confi dence intervals are incorrect, what can we say about CIs? The definition of a confidence interval makes clear how to in terpret a confidence procedure. However, when we compute a specific interval from the data and must interpret it, we are faced with difficulty. It is not obvious how to move from our knowledge of the properties of the confidence procedure to the interpretation of the confidence interval.
Textbook authors and proponents of confidence intervals bridge the gap seamlessly by claiming that the properties of confidence procedures can be applied to individual con fidence intervals. For instance, Masson and Loftus 2003 state that the interpretation of the confidence interval con structed around that specific mean would be that there is a 95 probability that the interval is one of the 95 of all pos sible confidence intervals that includes the population mean. Put more simply, in the absence of any other information, there is a 95 probability that the obtained confidence inter val includes the population mean. Cumming 2014 writes that we can be 95 confident that our interval includes
2
This confidence procedure makes use of the fact that there is

a 50 probability that xfalls within 55 21.46 meters
of the hatch. The rescuers alert the statistician that the first two bubbles have been observed, as shown in Figure 2B. The bubbles are almost 10 meters apart.
The statistician computes the confidence intervals using CP1 and CP2. The interval from CP1 is nearly as wide as it can possibly be. At first, the statistician despairs, thinking that the first two bubbles have led to extremely imprecise in formation. But then the statistician notes that the width of the interval from CP2 never changes, confusingly suggesting that the width of the CI need not be function of precision in the data.
Faced with seemingly contradictory information from the two CIs about the precision of the estimate x , the statistician decides to follow a different line of reasoning. Thinking her CP2 superior due to the fact that it directly used information about the width of the submersible, she reasons about the likely values for the location of the hatch. She believes that by virtue of being contained in her interval, the values inside the confidence interval should all be taken seriously as esti mates of the hatch location. This second, widelymistaken interpretation of intervalsthat specific parameters in the interval are likely or plausiblewe dub the likelihood error:
Myth 2 The Likelihood Error A confidence interval contains the likely values for the parameter. Values inside the confidence interval are more likely than those outside. This error exists in several varieties, sometimes involving plausibility, credibility, or reasonableness of beliefs about the parameter.
Loftus 1996, for instance, says that the CI gives an indi cation of how seriously the observed pattern of means should be taken as a reflection of the underlying pattern of popula tion means. This logic is used when when confidence inter vals are used to test theory Velicer et al., 2008 or to argue for the null or practically null hypothesis Loftus, 1996. The problem with the logic of the likelihood error is that a confidence interval may contain impossible values, or may exclude values that are just as plausible as ones inside the interval. For instance, the CI for the first submarine failed to contain most of the likely values, leading the statistician to believe his estimate was very precise.

the parameter and can think of the lower and upper limits as likely lower and upper bounds for the parameter.
This interpretation, although seemingly natural, is incor rect. We dub this incorrect reasoning the Fundamental Con fidence Fallacy FCF. The FCF is fundamental because it seems to flow naturally from the definition of the confidence interval:
Myth 3 The Fundamental Confidence Fallacy If the probability that a random interval contains the true value is X, then the plausibility or probability that a particular observed interval contains the true value is also X.
The reasoning behind the Fundamental Confidence Fal lacy seems plausible: on a given sample, we could get any one of the possible confidence intervals. Because 95 of the possible confidence intervals contain the true value, without any other information it seems reasonable to say that we have 95 certainty that the true value is in our calculated confi dence interval. This interpretation is suggested by the name confidence interval itself: the word confident, in lay use, is closely related to concepts of plausibility and belief. The name confidence interval therefore invites the FCF as an interpretation.
The first hint that the FCF is a fallacy is the fact that, as we have seen, for any given problem there could be more than one confidence procedure. If the mere fact that a confidence procedure has a confidence coefficient of X implied that any interval computed from that procedure has a X prob ability of containing the true parameter value, then two in tervals computed with the same data from two different 50 confidence procedures will both have a 50 probability of containing the true value.
Consider CP1 and CP2; both are centered around x . If in tervals from CP1 and CP2 both have a 50 probability of containing the true value, then the laws of probability re quire that all of the 50 probability be concentrated in the shorter of the two intervalsotherwise, the longer of the two intervals would have50 probability of containing the true value. This seems to imply that if we have two pro cedures that are always nested within one another, as CP1 and CP2 are, then we can simply take the shorter of the twowhichever that isas our 50 CI. But since both CP1 and CP2 are 50 CIs, then the procedure taking the shorter of the two must contain the true value less than 50 of the time, meaning it cannot be a 50 confidence procedure. The FCF leads to contradiction.
We do not need two confidence procedures to see why the FCF is a fallacy. In the second submarine scenario, a statistician using CP1 under the FCF would believe, on the basis that she has computed a 50 CI, that she is 50 certain that the true value is between the two bubbles. Considering the fact that bubbles cannot be more than 5 meters from the hatch, if the bubbles are more than 5 meters apart a CI com
puted from CP1 must contain the hatch location. All CIs from CP1 that are wider than 5 meters contain , with cer tainty. Under the FCF, the data would yield both 100 cer tainty and 50 certainty. Likewise, in the first scenario, the bubbles were only 0.05 meters apart. Of confidence intervals that are 0.05 meters wide, only 5 contain the true value see the supplement for an explanation. On the basis of this fact, one could state 5 certainty that the hatch is in the interval, and yet the FCF would lead one to also claim 50 certainty. The FCF leads to multiple, contradictory inferences from the same data.
The Fundamental Confidence Fallacy seems to follow di rectly from the definition of a confidence interval. How can one use a confidence procedure that yields 50 CIs, yet not be 50 certain that they contain the true value? We explore the roots of this seeming paradox.
Relevant subsets
You may have heard the old joke about the statistician who drowned wading across a river. He knew that the river was one meter deep…on average. The joke works as far as it goes because anyone can see that the statistician was foolish for considering only the average depth of the river. Surely at some point he could see that the water was dangerously deep and yet he pressed on, presumably reassured by the sophisti cation of his research into the depth of the river.
The statistician in the joke failed to use relevant depth of the river at his location to inform his actions. The Fundamen tal Confidence Fallacy entails a similar confusion: the con fusion of the average properties of a confidence procedure with what is known about a particular confidence interval. Consider the submarine example: if we were to know that the width of the confidence interval from CP1 had a width of 9 meters, should we report 50 confidence in the interval, or 100 confidence? It is a 50 CI in the sense that it was generated from a 50 confidence procedure. If we restrict our attention to intervals of width 9 meters, however, we find that 100 of these intervals contain the true value.
Fisher 1959b argued that probability statements like the ones above were critically flawed. In particular, upon ob serving the data, one can see that the observed data are part of a subset of data space that is, possible data for which the CI has a different probability of containing the true value than the average probability. In the submarine example, these subsets can be identified by how far apart the bubbles were. In cases like these, the subset into which the data fall is rel evant to judging the probability that the CI contains the true value; hence, these special subsets of the data are called rel evant subsets Buehler, 1959; BuehlerFeddersen, 1963; Casella, 1992; Robinson, 1979.
The existence of relevant subsets indicates a failure of properly conditioning on the data: there is the information in data that is not being used. By not using this relevant
FUNDAMENTAL CONFIDENCE FALLACY 5

6 MOREY ET AL.
information, researchers who believe the Fundamental Con fidence Fallacy are blinding themselves to important aspects of the data. Someone who wanted to make good use of their data would surely never want to use an interval that admitted relevant subsets, because that would involve ignoring what could be plainly seen in the data. Furthermore, if one be lieves the Fundamental Confidence Fallacy, the existence of relevant subsets can cause mutually contradictory confidence statements.
Although there is nothing about confidence procedures themselves that prevent relevant subsetstheir goal is a long run average performance, not to support reasonable, specific inferenceswe can create a procedure that eliminates the relevant subsets in the submersible example. Bayesian in tervals called credible intervals take into account all the data through conditioning. If we take the central 50 of the inter vals labeled posterior in Figure 2, we obtain the following credible interval4:
x1x2 x 5 2
The credible intervals for the first and second submarine res cue scenarios are shown in Figure 2 along the line labeled Cred. Int. Notice that the Bayesian credible interval prop erly tracks the precision given by the data as shown by the posterior. Incidentally, this Bayesian credance procedure yields another 50 confidence procedure.
It is clear that to a scientist caring primarily about what the data at hand say about the parameter, the Bayesian in terval is preferable. The Bayesian interval does not ignore the information in the data by leaving relevant subsets; it cannot include impossible values; and its narrowness is di rectly proportional to the precision implied by the data. It is derived from the Bayesian posterior distribution, which is a unique statement about the uncertainty about the parameter, given the data and a prior. In contrast, confidence intervals are not unique; for any given problem, there may be several mutually contradictory confidence procedures. Finally, the Bayesian interval, through its use of a prior, has the interpre tation that the advocates of desire: that the plausibility that the true value is within the interval is 50.
We will explore the properties of Bayesian procedures in the Discussion; for now, we present a scenario that will be more familiar to psychological researchers: Normal data with the Students t confidence interval.
Example 2: Students t interval
The submarine example was specifically tailored to show how each of the three broad claims about confidence inter vals fail. Many users of CIs, however, will never encounter such a problem. Their data is roughly normal, and so they use Students t confidence interval almost exclusively. As we will argue in the discussion, this does not make the argument
against CIs less powerful: CIs are advocated as a general in ferential tool, so they should work generally. If CIs only ap pear to make good inferences in a small number of circum scribed situations, their logical basis is suspect. Moreover, the propenents of CIs often directly state or indirectly imply that all CPs have the properties erroneously ascribed to them, by virtue of them being CIs see, for example, Cumming, 2014, who states that these properties generally apply to any CI. It turns out, however, that the contradictory con clusions caused by relevant subsets occur even with popular Students t confidence interval.
Consider a situation in which N2 observations are to be drawn from a normal distribution with unknown meanand standard deviation . As previously discussed, the typical 50 Students t confidence procedure for these data is
s x1x2 x x
22
,
or simply the minimum observation to the maximum obser vation. The fact that this is a 50 confidence procedure im plies that if we observe the data, compute the CI, and then make the dichotomous claim the CI contains the true value,or, alternatively, the CI does not contain the true value our claim will be correct 50 of the time, on average. If relevant subsets exist, then we can find a way to improve our accuracy above 50 correct by only using information in the data.
Although we did not previously point it out, we have al ready presented the evidence of relevant subsets using Stu dents t intervals. If we reexamine Figure 1, it is apparent that the intervals near the bottom of the figurethe short intervalsalmost never contain the true value. The longer intervals near the top, in contrast, almost always contain the true value. In general, the probability that a Students t CI contains the true value is an increasing function of the stan dard error.
In order to exploit this fact, we require a way of separating short intervals from long ones. Buehler 1959 suggested a simple strategy for improving on the 50 accuracy of the CI: pick a positive numberany positive number will doand if the sample standard deviation s is larger than this number, claim that the interval contains the true value. If the standard deviation is smaller the selected number, claim that the interval excludes the true value. No matter what the true mean, true standard deviation, and positive number one selects, this strategy will lead to a greater than 50 success rate for selecting intervals that do or do not contain the true value.
How far can you raise your accuracy above the nominal 50 correct rate for the confidence interval? The accuracy
4This credible interval is formed by assuming a prior distribu tion that assigns equal plausibility to all possible values of . A derivation is provided in the supplement to this article.

of the strategy depends on the number you selected to sep arate the short intervals from the long ones. If the number you selected is near .67, you can win about 34 of the time. Your accuracy will drop as your criterion moves further from this optimal value. The proof of this fact is not provided by Buehler 1959, but we have provided it in the supple ment because it will help understand why the relevant subsets arise.
Given that your accuracy depends on how well you can guess the true population standard deviation , it might seem that increasing your accuracy above 50 requires prior infor mation about . It is important to emphasize that the prob ability that you are correct with Buehlers strategy is always greater than 50, no matter what the criterion. It is true, however, that it is bounded at .5. If you are very, very far off in your guess of , then your accuracy will be negligi bly larger than 50. This boundedness has led statisticians to call this relevant subset a semirelevant subset Buehler, 1959; Robinson, 1979, which is typically considered less problematic than fully relevant subsets, where the probability is bounded away from 50. This might cause one to suspect that the problem is not as bad as it might first seem; certainly, the problem with Students t intervals does not seem as dire as it was with the CI in the submarine rescue example.
There are two responses to this defense of the Students t confidence interval. First, as Buehler 1959 points out, in formation about the error in ones measurementswhatever these measurements might beis precisely the kind of infor mation that is known to a competent experimenter, and that would garner rough agreement across experimenters. One does not need very specialized knowledge ofto increase ones accuracy substantially above 50. If, for instance, you underestimateby a factor of 10a very large underesti mation that we suspect most experimentalists would be able to beatyour accuracy will still about 55. A statistician may find this semirelevant subset less interesting, but a sci entist concerned with making reasonable, accurate inferences should find it disconcerting.
The second response to the defense against the Students t CIs semirelevant subsets is that in fact, the Students t CI admits fully relevant subsets. We presented the semirelevant subset first for conceptual clarity. Consider the following scheme, suggested by Pierce 1973. Suppose we sample N2 observations from a normal population with unknown mean and variance, then compute a 50 Students t confi dence interval. We then simultaneously perform a twosided t test against the null hypothesis that 0 it is irrelevant whether or not we are interested in the hypothesis that 0. If the p value for the t test is greater than .25, then the proba bility that the 50 confidence interval contains the true value is greater than or equal to 23, regardless of the true mean and standard deviation of the population. In a similar but more dramatic fashion to Buehlers 1959 example, the procedure
selects for large CIs by requiring a large p value.5
Pierces 1973 relevant subset shows that even with the Students t confidence interval, one could claim with 50 certainty that the true mean is within the CI, and simulta neously know that the data are part of a relevant subset for which CIs contain the true mean with a probability of at least 23. Confidence procedures fail because they can provide contradictory advice on how confident we should be that the true value is inside the interval. Indeed, confidence proce dures were not designed to offer such advice. Confidence procedures were merely designed to allow the analyst to make certain kinds of dichotomous statements about whether an interval contains the true value, in such a way that the statements are true a fixed proportion of the time on aver age Neyman, 1937. Expecting them to do anything else is
expecting too much.
Inference without Relevant Subsets
Relevant subsets threaten the coherence and uniqueness of frequentist inferences with confidence intervals and can be thought of as an example of a more general problem, the ref erence class problem Venn, 1888. Frequentist probability is defined as a longrun proportion, or the number of events that occur with a specified property e.g., CIs that contain the true value out of some reference class of events. If there are rel evant subsets, then there are multiple probability statements we could make Fisher, 1959a, depending on the reference class we choose.
The submarine example makes the implications clear. Is our reference class all CIs, in which case 50 of CIs will contain the true value? Or is our reference class all CIs with a particular width, in which case anywhere from 0 for very narrow CIs to 100 for CIs wider than 5 meters? Either confidence statement is valid, from a frequentist perspective, but they contradict one another.
It seems clear that restricted reference classes are the preferable: when possible, our inferences should be based on the most specific descriptions of the data possible. One might be tempted to try to solve the problem simply: if our data are part of a known relevant subset, then we should con dition our inference on that fact. In Pierces 1973 example above, if p.25, then we should report a confidence of greater than or equal to 23. However, this is no solution; an observation may be a member of multiple overlapping rele vant subsets, and then the reference class problem rears its ugly head again.
The desire to base inference only on the data that were ob served, and not on the average properties across all possible data sets, suggests a simple solution to the relevant subset
5If, like the authors of this paper, you find this result unbeliev able and counterintuitive, R code is provided in the supplement to show the result by simulation.
FUNDAMENTAL CONFIDENCE FALLACY 7

8 MOREY ET AL.
problem. There is one reference class that is as specific as possible that makes the relevant subsets problem disappear: the data itself. Bayesian inference, for instance, makes use of Bayes theorem, which states that
py pyp, py
where y is the data andis a vector of unknown parameters. The posterior py yields a probability distribution that represents the uncertainty about the parameters, given the ob served data. The prior, p, represents our uncertainty about the parameters before observing the data. If the prior prob ability distribution is properthat is, it represents a valid probability distributionthen there can be no relevant sub sets Casella, 1992; Robinson, 1979. The probability state ments that arise from Bayesian inference with proper priors must be unique and consistent. Furthermore, the interpre tation of probability statements that arise from Bayesian in ference are interpretable as statements of plausibility, unlike frequentist probability statements which have no such inter pretation.
Notice, though, that in order to rid ourselves the relevant subsets that make can make reasoning from confidence inter vals problematic, we require a prior distribution, p. As we have argued elsewhere Rouder, Morey, Verhagen, Province,Wagenmakers, submitted, reasonable inference requires bringing information to the table. Only if we bring informa tion to the table, in the form of a reasonable prior distribution, can we take all the information off the table. The belief that one can make inferences without committing to using prior information strikes us like a gambler who tries to win without paying the ante. The rules of the table, unfortunately, do not allow this.
The argument presented herethat frequentist infer ence, in this case with CIsleads to incoherent infer ences, is but one of a number of arguments for moving away from frequentist inferential methods. Elsewhere, we have argued for Bayesian inference as a viable replace ment de VriesMorey, 2013; M. LeeWagenmakers, 2005; Morey, Rouder, Verhagen,Wagenmakers, in press; Rouder, Speckman, Sun, Morey,Iverson, 2009; RouderMorey, 2011; Rouder, Morey, Speckman,Province, 2012; Wagenmakers, 2007; Wagenmakers, M. D. Lee, Lodewyckx,Iverson, 2008; Wagenmakers, Wetzels, Borsboom,van der Maas, 2011. A full accounting of Bayesian inference is beyond the scope of this article; for the interested reader, in addition to the articles just mentioned we also recommend Dienes 2011, P. M. Lee 2004, and Edwards, Lindman, and Savage 1963.
Discussion
Using two examples, we have shown that confidence in tervals do not have the properties that are often claimed on
their behalf. Confidence intervals were developed to solve a very constrained problem: how can one construct an in terval that contains the true mean a fixed proportion of the time? This definition, which concerns only average perfor mance, does not support reasonable inference from specific data. Claims that confidence intervals yield an impression of precision, that the values within them are plausible, and that the confidence coefficient can be read as a measure of cer tainty that the interval contains the true value, are all errors.
Good intentions underlie the advocacy of confidence in tervals: it would be excellent to have procedures with the properties claimed. The FCF is driven by a desire to as sess the plausibility that an interval contains the true value; the likelihood error is driven by a desire to determine which values of the parameter are likely; and the precision error is driven by a desire to quantify the precision of the estimates. We support these goals Morey et al., in press, but CIs are not the way to achieve them.
Confidence intervals versus credible intervals
One of the misconceptions regarding the relationship be tween Bayesian inference and frequentist inference is that they will lead to the same inferences. In the case where data are normally distributed, for instance, there is a particular prior that will lead to a confidence interval that is numeri cally identical to Bayesian credible intervals computed using the Bayesian posterior Jeffreys, 1961; Lindley, 1965. This occurs, for instance, in the Students t scenario described above.6 Thismightleadonetosuspectthatitdoesnotmatter whether one uses confidence procedures or Bayesian proce dures.
If researchers were only expected to study phenomena that were normally distributed, and researchers were only expected to make a single inference from the datathe con fidence intervalthen inference by confidence procedures might seem indistinguishable from inference by Bayesian procedures. The defense of confidence procedures by noting that, in some restricted cases, they numerically correspond to Bayesian procedures is actually no defense at all. One must first choose which confidence procedure, of many, to use, and if one is committed to the procedure that corresponds to Bayesian inference, then this is an admission that it was the Bayesian procedure that was desired all along. More broadly, if psychologists are to be sophisticated statistical thinkers, they should not be limited to a single inferential statement under restrictive assumptions.
6The fact that the confidence interval and objective Bayesian credible interval are numerically the same might lead one to believe that Bayesian intervals are susceptible to relevant subsets as well. However, the objective Bayesian interval is not a proper probability distribution. Bayesian inference with proper priors will be immune to relevant subsets.

Loftus 1993 argued in the context of recommending abandoning significance testing, that limiting ourselves to common designs and assumptions e.g., normal populations severely limits the inferences we can make. To prevent ar bitrary limitations on statistical inferences, if Bayesian inter pretations are desired, Bayesian inference should be applied in its full generalitynot just when it numerically corre sponds with frequentist inference. The correspondence be tween confidence procedures and Bayesian procedures is not a general rule. In some cases, for instance with count data, there are many different confidence intervals among others the Wald, the AgrestiCoull, the ClopperPearson, the arc sine, and the logit; see Brown, Cai,DasGupta, 2001, for a review. These confidence procedures all yield different in ferences among themselves, not to mention differences with Bayesian credible intervals.
In some cases confidence procedures do not even allow an inference. The endpoints of a confidence interval are al ways set by the data. Suppose, however, we are interested in determining the plausibility that a parameter is in a par ticular range; for instance, in the United States, it is against the law to execute criminals who are intellectually disabled. The criterion used for intellectual disability in the US state of Florida is having an IQ lower than 70. Since IQ is measured with error, one might ask what confidence we have that a particular criminals IQ is between 0 and 70. In this case, the interval is no longer a function of the sample. The long run probability that the true value is inside a fixed interval is unknown and is either 0 or 1, and hence no CP can be constructed, even though such information may be critically important to a researcher, policy maker, or criminal defen dant.
Even in seemingly simple cases where a fixed interval is nested inside a CI, or vice versa, one cannot draw conclu sions about the confidence of a fixed interval. One might assume that an interval nested within a CI must have lower confidence than the CI; however, in the second submersible rescue scenario, a 100 confidence interval all the possi ble values ofwas nested within both CI1 and CI2, which were 50 CIs. Likewise, one might believe that if a CI is nested within a fixed interval, then the fixed interval must have greater confidence than the interval. In the first sub mersible rescue scenario, intervals within which the 50 CI1 were nested had low plausibility, due to their narrowness. In contrast, Bayesian procedures offer the ability to compute the plausibility of any given range of values, and are guaran teed to yield statements that are mutually coherent. Because all inferences must be made through Bayes theorem, infer ences must remain internally consistent c.f. StoneDawid, 1972.
Finally, we believe that in science, the meaning of our inferences are important. Bayesian credible intervals sup port an interpretation of probability in terms of plausibility,
thanks to the explicit use of a prior. Confidence intervals, on the other hand, are based on a philosophy that does not allow inferences about plausibility, but do not require a prior. Using confidence intervals as if they were credible intervals is an attempt to smuggle Bayesian meaning into frequentist statistics, without proper consideration of a prior. Priors have consequences, and must be carefully considered. There is no free lunch; to get reasonable inference, one must pay a price Rouder, Morey, Verhagen, et al., submitted.
Conclusion
We have suggested that confidence intervals do not sup port the inferences that their advocates believe they do. The problems with confidence intervalsparticularly the fact that they admit can relevant subsetsshows a fatal flaw with their logic. They cannot be used to draw reasonable inferences. We recommend that their use be abandoned.
We therefore take stock of what we would be giving up, if we were to give up the use of confidence procedures. Aban doning the use of confidence procedures means abandoning a method that merely allows us to create intervals that con tain the true value with a fixed longrun probability. We sus pect that if researchers understand that this is the only thing they will be losing, they will not consider it a great loss. By adopting Bayesian inference, they will gain a way of making principled statements about precision and plausibility. Ulti mately, this is exactly what the advocates of CIs have wanted all along.
References
Berger, J. O.Wolpert, R. L. 1988. The likelihood princi ple 2nd ed. Hayward, CA: Institute of Mathematical Statistics.
Brown, L. D., Cai, T. T.,DasGupta, A. 2001. Interval es timation for a binomial proportion. Statistical Science, 162, 101133.
Buehler, R. J. 1959. Some validity criteria for statistical in ferences. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 304, 845863.
Buehler, R. J.Feddersen, A. P. 1963. Note on a condi tional property of Students t1. The Annals of Mathe matical Statistics, 343, 10981100.
Casella, G. 1992. Conditional inference from confidence sets. Lecture NotesMonograph Series, 17, 112. Cumming, G. 2014. The new statistics: Why and how. Psy
chological Science.
Cumming, G.Finch, S. 2005. Inference by eye: confi
dence intervals and how to read pictures of data. Amer
ican Psychologist, 602, 170180.
de Vries, R. M.Morey, R. D. 2013. Bayesian hypoth
esis testing for singlesubject designs. Psychological Methods, 182, 165185.
FUNDAMENTAL CONFIDENCE FALLACY 9

10 MOREY ET AL.
Dienes, Z. 2011. Bayesian versus orthodox statistics: Which side are you on? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6, 274290.
Edwards, W., Lindman, H.,Savage, L. J. 1963. Bayesian statistical inference for psychological research. Psy chological Review, 70, 193242.
Fidler, F.Loftus, G. R. 2009. Why figures with er ror bars should replace p values: some conceptual ar guments and empirical demonstrations. Zeitschrift fu r Psychologie, 2171, 2737.
Fisher, R. A. 1959a. Mathematical probability in the natural sciences. Metrika, 21, 110.
Fisher, R. A. 1959b. Statistical Methods and Scientific In ference Second. Edinburgh, UK: Oliver and Boyd.
Jeffreys, H. 1961. Theory of probability 3rd edition. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lee, M.Wagenmakers, E.J. 2005. Bayesian statisti cal inference in psychology: Comment on Trafimow 2003. Psychological Review, 112, 662668.
Lee, P. M. 2004. Bayesian statistics: An introduction 3rd ed. New York: Wiley.
Lindley, D. V. 1965. Introduction to probability and statis tics from a Bayesian point of view, part 2: Inference. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Loftus, G. R. 1993. A picture is worth a thousand pvalues: On the irrelevance of hypothesis testing in the com puter age. Behavior Research Methods, Instrumenta tion and Computers, 25, 250256.
Loftus, G. R. 1996. Psychology will be a much better sci ence when we change the way we analyze data. Cur rent directions in psychological science, 5, 161171.
Masson, M. E. J.Loftus, G. R. 2003. Using confi dence intervals for graphically based data interpreta tion. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology, 57, 203220.
Morey, R. D., Rouder, J. N., Verhagen, J.,Wagenmakers, E.J. in press. Why hypothesis tests are essential for psychological science: a comment on Cumming. Psy chological Science.
Neyman, J. 1934. On the two different aspects of the rep resentative method: the method of stratified sampling and the method of purposive selection. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 974, 558625.
Neyman, J. 1937. Outline of a theory of statistical estima tion based on the classical theory of probability. Philo sophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series A, Mathematical and Physical Sciences, 236, 333380.
Pierce, D. A. 1973. On some difficulties in a frequency the ory of inference. The Annals of Statistics, 12, 241 250.
Psychonomics Society. 2012. Psychonomic Society guide lines on statistical issues.
Robinson, G. K. 1979. Conditional properties of statistical procedures. The Annals of Statistics, 74, 742755.
Rouder, J. N.Morey, R. D. 2011. A Bayes factor meta analysis of Bems ESP claim. Psychonomic BulletinReview, 18, 682689.
Rouder, J. N., Morey, R. D., Speckman, P. L.,Province, J. M. 2012. Default Bayes factors for ANOVA de signs. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 56, 356 374.
Rouder, J. N., Morey, R. D., Verhagen, J., Province, J. M.,Wagenmakers, E.J. submitted. The p.05 rule and the hidden costs of the free lunch in inference.
Rouder, J. N., Speckman, P. L., Sun, D., Morey, R. D.,Iverson, G. 2009. Bayesian ttests for accepting and rejecting the null hypothesis. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 16, 225237.
Stone, M.Dawid, A. P. 1972. UnBayesian implications of improper Bayes inference in routine statistical prob lems. Biometrika, 592, 369375.
Velicer, W. F., Cumming, G., Fava, J. L., Rossi, J. S., Prochaska, J. O.,Johnson, J. 2008. Theory testing using quantitative predictions of effect size. Applied Psychology, 574, 589608.
Venn, J. 1888. The logic of chance 3rd. London: Macmil lan.
Wagenmakers, E.J. 2007. A practical solution to the per vasive problem of p values. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 14, 779804.
Wagenmakers, E.J., Lee, M. D., Lodewyckx, T.,Iver son, G. 2008. Bayesian versus frequentist inference. In H. Hoijtink, I. Klugkist,P. Boelen Eds., Prac tical Bayesian approaches to testing behavioral and social science hypotheses pp. 181207. New York: Springer.
Wagenmakers, E.J., Wetzels, R., Borsboom, D.,van der Maas, H. 2011. Why psychologists must change the way they analyze their data: The case of psi. A com ment on Bem 2011. Journal of Personality and So cial Psychology, 100, 426432.
Welch, B. L. 1939. On confidence limits and sufficiency, with particular reference to parameters of location. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 101, 5869.
Wilkinson, L.the Task Force on Statistical Inference. 1999. Statistical methods in psychology journals: Guidelines and explanations. American Psychologist, 54, 594604.
Young, K. D.Lewis, R. J. 1997. What is confidence? part 1: the use and interpretation of confidence intervals. Annals of Emergency Medicine, 303, 307310.

Reviews

There are no reviews yet.

Only logged in customers who have purchased this product may leave a review.

Shopping Cart
[SOLVED] 代写 R algorithm Scheme math graph statistic Bayesian theory The Fallacy of Placing Confidence in Confidence Intervals
30 $